I’m going to discuss the
Euthyphro dilemma by comparing and contrasting two different atheists on
morality. Let’s begin by outlining the nature of the so-called dilemma.
If, on the one hand, God
commands or forbids something because it’s right or wrong, then it’s right and
wrong apart God. God is not the ultimate source of morality. Rather, God
himself is subject to a more ultimate standard.
If, on
the other hand, God’s bare command or prohibition is what makes something right
or wrong, then good and evil are arbitrary and vacuous. Arbitrary because
there’s no underlying rationale for the command or prohibition. And that, in
turn, renders good and evil meaningless, for they are consistent with any
command or opposing command.
Here is how a prominent atheist
states the alleged dilemma, with special emphasis on one horn of the alleged
dilemma:
Translated into contemporary terms, the question Socrates is asking is this: Are morally good actions morally good simply in virtue of God’s favoring them? Or does God favor them because they are–independently of his favoring them–morally good?Divine command theory says that what is good is good only because God has commanded it; there is nothing more to an act’s being good than that God command it.[According to] divine independence theory, the goodness of an action is a feature that is independent of, and antecedent to God’s willing it.The two theories differ on what accounts for this congruence. DCT says that it is God’s command that explains why the good acts are good, while DIT says that it is the goodness of the acts that explains why God commanded them.The way to bring out the difference is to consider a case of an act that we’d all antecedently agree is morally wrong–say, torturing an innocent child. If DCT is correct, then the following counterfactual is true: If God had commanded us to torture innocent children, then it would have been morally right to do so. DIT, however, entails the following: If God had commanded us to torture innocent children, then God would not have been perfectly good.Only the theorist who believes that right and wrong are independent of God’s commands could have any basis for thinking she or he knows in advance what God would or would not command. If, as DCT says, an act’s being good just consists in its being chosen by God, then there’s nothing about the action in advance of its being chosen or rejected that would enable us to determine what attitude God would take toward it in some other possible world. “Good” for the divine command theorist is synonymous with “commanded by God.” …there is nothing that is inherently good or bad, and thus nothing that explains God’s choosing which acts to endorse and which acts to prohibit.I doubt that there are many people who really believe DCT. If there were, then there would be fewer interpretive difficulties surrounding those stores in the Bible that depict God commanding actions that we would ordinarily take to be moral atrocities.The Bible is full of accounts of God’s killing, displacing, or otherwise seriously smiting presumably innocent people who had the misfortune of belonging to a tribe whose leaders had threatened to impede his ambitions for the Israelites…Sometimes, there’s not even a pretext that the doomed people are morally at fault: The only “crime” committed by the Canaanites was living in a land God wanted for his people.The question can be asked, then, Why ought one to obey God? The fact that this question can be asked, that it’s comprehensible, that it makes sense, is sufficient proof that the mere existence of an all-powerful Creator is not enough to generate a realm of moral fact.
Louise Antony, “Atheist as
Perfect Piety,” R. Garcia & N. King, Is Goodness Without God Good Enough?:
A Debate on Faith, Secularism, and Ethics (Rowman & Littlefield 2009), 71,72,73,79,80.
Before introducing the second
atheist, I’m going to comment on these excerpts:
i) She says torturing an
innocent child is something “we’d all antecedently agree is morally wrong.” But
as an atheist, she’s in no position to posit that claim. For one thing, it
seems to be empirically false. After all, there are people who torture innocent
children. Do they think what they are doing is morally wrong?
ii) Furthermore, even if we
think it’s morally wrong, that doesn’t make it morally wrong. From an atheistic
standpoint, we might say natural selection brainwashed us into cherishing
children because that sentiment promotes the survival of the species. But once
you become aware of the fact that you were brainwashed, you no longer feel
obliged to comply with your conditioning.
iii) In addition, there are
secular utilitarians who could propose a scenario in which it’s morally
permissible or even obligatory to torture a child. Take a variation on the
ticking timebomb scenario. A terrorist won’t divulge the information needed to
prevent nuking Chicago unless we torture, or threaten to torture, his child.
The harm done to one child is offset by the harm done to thousands of children
unless we torture his child.
iv) She also cites biblical
commands which she classifies as “moral atrocities.” But Bible writers didn’t
think those were moral atrocities.
v) Furthermore, many
cultures, both ancient and modern, commit similar “atrocities.” Do the
perpetrators think they are committing “moral atrocities?
So it’s hard for her to come
up with any cases “we’d all antecedently agree is morally wrong.”
I’m not being pedantic, here.
She’s not entitled to systematically beg the question when illustrating her
thesis. She needs to discharge her burden of proof.
vi) She says no pretext for
executing the Canaanites is even given. But that’s willfully ignorant. The
divine command is not a bare command. It supplies a rationale, implicating the
Canaanites in idolatry and immorality.
vii) She also says “there’s
nothing about the action in advance of its being chosen or rejected that would
enable us to determine what attitude God would take toward it in some other
possible world.”
But that confuses the
epistemology of ethics with the ontology of ethics. Whether something is good
or bad, and whether we know ahead of time whether it’s good or bad are separate
issues.
viii) Finally, she makes the
eccentric claim the mere ability to ask why we ought to obey God is sufficient
proof that the mere existence of an all-powerful Creator is not enough to
generate a realm of moral fact.
But that’s confused. At one
level we can simply accept the morality of a divine command on the authority of
a wise and benevolent God. That’s sufficient reason for us to accept it.
But that doesn’t make the
command itself groundless. God can have good reason for what he commands. And
knowing that God has a good reason is distinct from knowing what reason he has.
ix) There’s also a difference
between moral imperatives and a moral obligation to obey a divine command. We
can have a moral obligation to obey a divine command even if the command itself
is not a moral imperative.
For instance, God commanding
Abraham to leave Ur is not, itself a moral absolute. Rather, God commanded
Abraham to leave Ur because Abraham leaving Ur is part of God’s long-range plan
to redeem the world. His command is purposeful.
Abraham has a duty to obey
God’s command, but not because leaving Ur is intrinsically obligatory. Rather,
God has a good reason for command Abraham to leave Ur. And Abraham ought to
trust God’s wisdom, even if God didn’t reveal his reason to Abraham.
x) Apropos (ix), that type of
obligation sidesteps the Euthyphro dilemma. God’s command to Abraham isn’t
arbitrary. Rather, God’s command is explicable in reference to God’s
overarching plan (whether or not that explanation is available to Abraham). By
the same token, it’s not independent of God.
Let’s now quote another
atheist:
If value is tied to life, its content will depend on particular forms of life, and the most salient reasons it gives us will depend, even in a realist conception, on our own form of life. This is how a realist account can accommodate one of the things that make subjectivism seem most plausible, namely the fact that what we find self-evidently valuable is overwhelmingly contingent on the biological specifics of our form of life. Human good and bad depend in the first instance on our natural appetites, emotions, capacities, and interpersonal bonds, If we were more like bees or lions, what seems good to us would be very different, a point that Street emphasizes.[Quoting Street]: “Imagine, for instance, that we had evolved more along the lines of lions, so that males in relatively frequent circumstances had a strong unreflective evaluative tendency to experience the killing of offspring that were not his own as “demanded” by the circumstances, and so that females, in turn, experienced no strong unreflective tendency to “hold it against” a male when he killed her offspring in such circumstances, on the contrary becoming receptive to his advances soon afterwards.”
T. Nagel, Mind and Cosmos
(Oxford 2012), 119.
i) Now what’s striking about
this argument is that it could easily be retrofitted to account for many Biblical
commands and prohibitions. Instead of blind evolution, we have a Creator God
who designed different types of creatures with corresponding appetites,
emotions, capacities, and interpersonal bonds. Human obligations would be keyed
to human nature–the nature with which God endowed us. Our duties would be
engineered into us.
That sidesteps the Euthyphro
dilemma, for commands and prohibitions of this kind aren’t good “only” because
they are commanded. There is “more to it” than the bare command. Rather, you
have an inherent obligation that’s inherent in the nature of the agent. Good
for the creature because that’s how the creature was made.
Conversely, this isn’t good
apart from God. Rather, it’s contingent on how God designed us.
ii) I’d add that this doesn’t
exhaust all types of divine commands. For example, Scripture commands us to be
holy because God is holy. What grounds that command is the nested relationship
between the divine exemplar and its human exemplification. If God is
good–indeed, the summum bonum–then it’s good to be an instance of God’s
goodness.
That, too, sidesteps the
Euthyphro dilemma. On the one hand this isn’t arbitrary or vacuous. It’s
grounded in God’s own nature. But by the same token, it’s not something over
and above God himself.
iii) Likewise, we have a
standing obligation to worship God–because God is intrinsically worthy of our
worship. That also sidesteps the Euthyphro dilemma. It’s not a good command for
the command’s sake. Rather, it’s imbedded in something ultimately greater. We
should love the good because it’s good. And God’s goodness is exemplary
goodness. There is no higher good, be it possible or actual.
I've always found WLC's retort that God is good more than sufficient. But this is more helpful. BTW Steve, I was hoping to get more of your perspective on that article by Wielenberg linked to last week. I read through it and it seemed to do much the same thing that you criticize above in your post:
ReplyDelete"i) She says torturing an innocent child is something “we’d all antecedently agree is morally wrong.” But as an atheist, she’s in no position to posit that claim."
Wielenberg noted at the outset of his article that he would not present any positive arguments for ethical facts, since his theistic opponents also accept those facts. The remainder of the article seems then to try to argue that God cannot be source of moral values and duties. What did you think?
Briefly, several issues:
Deletei) He appeals to possible worlds, yet he also says moral facts are brute facts. But what's the role of possible worlds in his appeal if not to lay a metaphysical foundation for moral facts? If moral facts are brute facts, then they are groundless. So what's the function of possible worlds in his argument?
ii) He appeals to evolutionary ethics at the end. But how does invoking a concrete evolutionary process mesh with his appeal to abstract possible worlds? He seems to be grasping at straws. Desperately snatching at unrelated concepts.
iii) To merely posit brute moral facts is arbitrary and question-begging. Why think there are brute moral facts in the first place? That's not something he's entitled to stipulate, with no further ado.
iv) But his problem is deeper. It's not just that positing brute moral facts is arbitrary and question-begging. Rather, his naturalistic evolutionary outlook positively undercuts objective moral norms, as secular philosophers like Michael Ruse, Sharon Street, and Thomas Nagel readily admit,
v) Then there's the ontological status of possible worlds in a godless reality. Why think they exist? What are they? These are questions I directed at Philothumper.
By contrast, it's much easier to embed possible worlds in a theistic framework.