Thursday, February 25, 2010

Free Will, Evil, and Divine Providence

Here are some excerpts from Derk Pereboom's essay on "Free Will, Evil, and Divine Providence."

HT: James Anderson

The Free Will Theodicy

A potential drawback for the rejection of libertarianism is that it rules out the free will theodicy, which is often thought to be the most powerful defense we have of divine goodness in the face of evil. The free will theodicy in systematized form dates back at least to early Christianity and perhaps to Zoroastrianism, and remains the most prominent of all theodicies.

On the most common version, God had the option of creating or refraining from creating libertarian significantly free beings -- beings with libertarian free will that can make choices between right and wrong. A risk incurred by creating such beings is that they might freely choose evil and the choice be unpreventable by God. Benefits include creatures having moral responsibility for their actions and being creators in their own right. Since the benefits outweigh the risks, God is morally justified in creating such significantly free beings, and he is not culpable when they choose wrongly.

But how plausible is this as a theodicy for the most horrible evils? If it isn’t very plausible, perhaps not much is relinquished by accepting a view that rules it out. A familiar problem is that many of the more horrible evils would not seem to be or result from freely willed decisions. People being injured and dying as a result of earthquake, volcanic eruptions, diseases – including mental illnesses that give rise to unfree immoral choices -- would not seem to result from freely willed decisions, and for this reason are standardly classified as natural as opposed to moral evils. But a further objection, raised by several critics, is that even if we have free will of the libertarian sort, and many of our choices are freely willed in this libertarian sense, the consequences of those decisions are preventable by God. In general, evil consequences are preventable effects of freely willed decisions. Or, God might intervene earlier on in the process.

Given the nature of libertarian free will, short of killing them or disabling their wills, God might not have been able to prevent the Nazi leadership from deciding to perpetrate genocide, but God could have nonetheless prevented or limited the genocide, by, say, by rendering the Nazi guns, trains, and gas chambers ineffective. One answer to this is Richard Swinburne’s, that if God were to regularly prevent such evils in this way, then we would not fully understand the kinds of consequences our decisions could have, and this would have considerable disvalue. But, one might argue, God might have intervened earlier yet in the process, by, for example, healing the bad effects of childhood abuse and trauma. Or rather than intervening, God might have designed us so that we were not nearly as vulnerable to experiences of this sort, and, more generally, less vulnerable to the kinds of psychological problems that play a role in motivating evil decisions.

Swinburne has developed a thorough response to these sorts of objections. He argues that it is not just freely willed decision tout court that has the relevantly high intrinsic value, but two characteristics in addition: freely willed decision’s accomplishing what the agent intended -- what he calls efficacious free will, and freely willed decision’s adjudicating between good and evil options each of which genuinely motivate the agent – serious free will, in his terminology.

Swinburne contends that it is serious and efficacious free will that has the intrinsic value high enough to justify God in sometimes not preventing the decidedly evil consequences of immoral decisions. His account is significant, for it does not avoid a proposal for the kind of value free will must possess to sustain the role in theodicy that so many believe it has. In his view, first of all, “the very fact of the agent having a free choice is a great good for the agent; and a greater good the more serious the kind of free will, even if it is incorrectly used.” Moreover, an agent “is an ultimate source in an even fuller way if the choices open to him cover the whole moral range, from the very good to the very wrong.” And indeed, “an agent who has serious and efficacious free will is in a much fuller way an ultimate source of the direction of things in the world” than one who does not. Furthermore, in preparation for his theodicy, Swinburne contends that:

It is a good for us if our experiences are not wasted but are used for the good of others, if they are the means of a benefit which would not have come to others without them, which will at least in part compensate for those experiences. It follows from this insight that it is a blessing for a person if the possibility of his suffering makes possible the good for others of having the free choice of hurting or harming them ... and of choosing to show or not show sympathy.”11

To illustrate the import of these claims for theodicy, Swinburne discusses the example of the slave trade from Africa in the eighteenth century. About this practice he writes -- in what is by now a well-known passage:

But God allowing this to occur made possible innumerable opportunities for very large numbers of people to contribute or not to contribute to the development of this culture; for slavers to choose to enslave or not; for plantation-owners to choose to buy slaves or not and to treat them well or ill; for ordinary white people and politicians to campaign for its abolition or not to bother, and to campaign for compensation for the victims or not to bother; and so on. There is also the great good for those who themselves suffered as slaves that their lives were not useless, their vulnerability to suffering made possibile many free choices, and thereby so many steps towards the formation of good or bad character.12

One problem for this line of thought is that it finds itself in opposition to strongly ingrained moral practice when horrible evil is at issue. First, as David Lewis points out, for us the evildoer’s freedom is a weightless consideration, not merely an outweighed consideration. When the slave traders come to take your children, and you are contemplating violent resistance, we do not expect you to consider the value of the slave traders’ efficacious but immoral free will, which would be high indeed if value of this sort could have the role in justifying God’s allowing the slave trade that Swinburne suggests it does. Moreover, if he is right, then when twenty slave traders have freely decided to try to take your children, ten times as much value of the sort he describes would be at stake as when there are only two, and there would be that much more reason not to resist. Moreover, all else being equal, there would be significantly less reason to harm in self-defense an opponent who appears to have free will then one who is known to be mentally ill and incapable of free decisions. None of this has a role in our ordinary moral practice.

A further problem for the free will theodicy is occasioned by Swinburne’s view that to choose freely to do what is right one must have a serious countervailing desire to refrain from doing what is right instead, strong enough that it could actually motivate a choice so to refrain. Swinburne thinks that this point supports the free will theodicy, since it can explain why God allows us to have desires to do evil, and, by extension, why God allows choices in accord with those desires.

But this claim rather serves to undermine the force of the free will theodicy as an explanation for many horrible evils. For we do not generally believe that the value of a free choice outweighs the disvalue of having desires to perform horribly evil actions, especially if they are strong enough to result in action. For example, the notion that it is more valuable than not for people to have a strong desire to abuse children for the reason that this gives them the opportunity to choose freely not to do so has no purchase on us. Our practice for people with desires of this sort is to provide them with therapy to diminish or eradicate such desires. We have no tendency to believe that the value of making a free decision not to abuse a child made in struggle against a desire to do so carries any weight against the proposal to provide this sort of therapy.

Furthermore, were we to encounter someone with a strong desire to abuse children but who nevertheless resisted actively seeking do so, we would not think that his condition has more value overall than one in which he never had the desire to abuse children in the first place.

Moreover, I daresay that a significant proportion of people alive today – well over 90% – has neither intentionally chosen a horrible evil nor had a genuine struggle with a desire to do so – they have never, for instance, tortured, maimed, or murdered, nor seriously struggled with desires to do so. But we do not think that their lives would have been more valuable had they possessed such desires even if every struggle against them had been successful. Thus it is questionable whether God would allow such desires in order to realize the value of certain free choices. This aspect of Swinburne’s theodicy may have some credibility with respect to evils that are not horrible, but much less, I think, when it comes to horrible evils. Here I would like to emphasize that if we thought free will did in fact have the proposed degree of intrinsic value, our moral practice would be decidedly different from what it is now — in ways that, given our moral sensibilities, we would find very disturbing.

Doing and Allowing

The libertarian view would appear to enjoy a considerable advantage precisely in making possible a theodicy for the consequences of freely willed evil decisions. For it need only grant that God allows these consequences, while divine determinism seems constrained to accept that God actively brings them about. When one envisions some particularly egregious past horror, it might be especially difficult to accept that God actively brought it about. I find it very difficult to reconcile myself to such particular claims. But is it any easier to reconcile oneself to the claim that God allows that specific horror? Suppose that you are subjected to abuse by someone who hates you. If the abuser had libertarian free will, then even though God did not actively bring about the decision to abuse you, God nevertheless allowed the consequences of this decision to occur while at the same time having the power to prevent them. In the divine determinist view, by contrast, God actively brings about these consequences. Factoring in providence, on the libertarian view, God allows the abuse to occur in order to realize a greater good, while on the determinist view, God actively brings it about in order to realize a greater good.

One should first note that while it is often held that actively bringing about or doing evil is prima facie morally worse than merely allowing evil, of course it is not as if allowing evil is generally morally permissible. Rather, in comparing the libertarian and determinist theological conceptions on this issue, the important question is this. Supposing that on the libertarian position God is justified in allowing evil consequences for the sake of some greater good, would it be morally worse for God actively to bring them about for the sake of that good?

The answer to this question depends at least in part on the nature of the good to be realized. In some cases God might well be justified in allowing the evil consequences, but not in actively bringing them about. By analogy, a parent might justifiably allow a child to play with matches, foreseeing that he might well incur a slight burn as a result, while it would be wrong for the parent to actively bring about that burn. But consider, for instance, the purported good of retributively justified punishment where the evil consequences in question are actively brought about by agents other than God who are not appropriate authorities for inflicting the punishment at issue. If these evils are to be justified as retributive punishment, it would actually seem better for God actively to bring them about than merely to allow these other agents to do so.

By analogy, if Lee Harvey Oswald did in fact kill John F. Kennedy, and if Oswald did deserve the death penalty, it would have been better for an appropriate authority to administer the penalty than for that authority to allow Jack Ruby to kill him. Assuming that God is an appropriate authority for punishment, it would then be better that God actively bring about some punishment than merely allow a person who is not an appropriate authority to do so.

Consider, furthermore, the good of soul-building that John Hick discusses. Suppose God knew that someone’s character would be significantly improved morally if he suffered in a certain way, and that God were justified in allowing the person to suffer on such grounds. Wouldn’t God then also be justified in actively bringing about the suffering on those grounds?

An apt analogy would seem to be that of say, Civil War surgery. Suppose the doctor knows that the patient will not survive unless he undergoes painful surgery. It is clearly not morally worse for the doctor to actually perform the surgery himself than it would be for him to allow another doctor to perform it.

Now indeed the intrinsic value of serious and efficacious free will would not be realizable if God actively caused rather than merely allowed the consequences of evil free decisions. But several key goods could be realized whether God actively brought about or merely allowed the suffering required for those goods, and for them it would appear at least as good for God to bring about the suffering as to allow it.

http://www.arts.cornell.edu/phil/homepages/pereboom/Providence.pdf

10 comments:

  1. "Factoring in providence, on the libertarian view, God allows the abuse to occur in order to realize a greater good, while on the determinist view, God actively brings it about in order to realize a greater good."

    I think this might be a bit of an oversimplification.

    Say a man desired to walk across the street to murder his neighbor. However, for that to happen, let's say several conditions need to be met:
    a) the neighbor needs to be home
    b) the murdering fellow needs to be in a possession of a weapon
    c) the neighbor's family must not be home

    I don't think the libertarian suggests that God allows these conditions to be met only if a greater good arises but rather that God doesn't intervene either way. Otherwise, it would be just a sort of "soft" determinism (or selective determinism). In reality, God may not interrupt natural events to provide that killer the weapon or stall his family so that they're unable to prevent the action, but neither does He strike the would-be murderer down with a bad case of the flu. God simply allows nature to take its course, for better or worse.

    On the other hand, the determinist might suggest that God moved in an active way so that the murder occurred (for whatever His reasons are). Let's say He stalled the family through bad weather, or made it easier for the man to find a weapon than nature running its own course would have otherwise allowed.

    In both instances, man really is free. The opportunity to commit wrongdoing is not relevant to whether one is willing to commit it. (Hence, Christ's warning on how committing adultery in the heart is identical to adultery in deed.)


    I'm wondering, though, if the serious determinist/Calvinist is also suggesting that God created the impulse within the man to commit the murder in the first place?

    ReplyDelete
  2. God can desire and intend that some event E occur and begin a causal chain ending in E while not necessarily desiring or intending any other event E* that E entails. But God's actively bringing about E doesn't entail that he actively brings about E* either.

    Suppose the G is the event of atonement of Christ, and the E's are any sin committed by a human person. God may only intend that G (the atonement) occurs, and simply instantiate one world with G in it from many without preference, so that none of the E's are intended or desired by him to occur.

    ReplyDelete
  3. I forgot to put: God can intend any greater good G while not intending or actively bringing about any evil E such that G ⊃ E.

    ReplyDelete
  4. "God simply allows nature to take its course, for better or worse."

    I'm not sure many libertarians would or could adopt this position. Any libertarian that wanted to affirm the doctrine of divine concurrence would have to say more than that God simply steps back and lets things play out all by themselves.

    But even on a libertarian scheme that denies divine concurrence, God still moved in at least one active way that brought about the murderous state of affairs: instantiating the world in which he knew this would occur.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Steven: "God can desire and intend that some event E occur and begin a causal chain ending in E while not necessarily desiring or intending any other event E* that E entails. But God's actively bringing about E doesn't entail that he actively brings about E* either."

    I'm not sure I understand this. If one wishes to arrive at a goal that requires prior actions/steps/conditions then it seems there will always be a sense in which one desires and actively pursues those prior conditions (as a means to the goal).

    If God's ultimate goal is redemption this requires a state in which man needs to be redeemed (a sinful state). It seems to me that this means God desires a sinful state so that he can achieve his goal: redemption. It may be the case that God does not ultimately desire the state of needing-redemption and he does not desire that state in and of itself, but he nonetheless desires its occurrence insofar has he desires redemption, which entails needing-redemption.

    ReplyDelete
  6. I'm not sure I understand this. If one wishes to arrive at a goal that requires prior actions/steps/conditions then it seems there will always be a sense in which one desires and actively pursues those prior conditions (as a means to the goal).

    Suppose that if I don't press a certain button at a nuclear reactor, then the core will explode and millions of people die. But suppose further that I know that if I were to press it, then I will be locked in a room and will be killed by some poison gas to be released from a central tank, or whatever.

    I want to save those millions of people. I press the button. Of course, my pressing the button entails that I die, but I don't thereby (i) desire my own death in anyway, nor do I (ii) intentionally bring about my death.

    I take it that intentionally bringing about some state of affairs involves my desiring that state of affairs to obtain--but since I don't desire my death, I don't intentionally bring it about.

    So also, God can intentionally bring about some state of affairs while not intentionally bringing about any evil states of affairs that obtain by entailment.

    ReplyDelete
  7. Suppose that if I don't press a certain button at a nuclear reactor, then the core will explode and millions of people die. But suppose further that I know that if I were to press it, then I will be locked in a room and will be killed by some poison gas to be released from a central tank, or whatever.

    I want to save those millions of people. I press the button. Of course, my pressing the button entails that I die, but I don't thereby (i) desire my own death in anyway, nor do I (ii) intentionally bring about my death.

    I take it that intentionally bringing about some state of affairs involves my desiring that state of affairs to obtain--but since I don't desire my death, I don't intentionally bring it about.

    So also, God can intentionally bring about some state of affairs while not intentionally bringing about any evil states of affairs that obtain by entailment.


    It seems to me that the fact that you pressed it is evidence that you do desire your death and intentionally bring it about, *not in an ultimate sense* but in a secondary sense of achieving your goal (or primary desire). If you were absolutely opposed or undesirous of dying (you were ultimately desiring to live), you wouldn't be willing to push the button under any conditions.

    I don't think we can isolate our desires or view actions or conditions in such an isolated manner.

    ReplyDelete
  8. I don't agree. I think that in such a case, I wouldn't desire my death though I would still be willing to die to save others.

    There is a difference between desiring some states of affairs and being willing to allow or bring about some state of affairs' obtaining.

    Or suppose I am holding some expensive porcelain family heirloom in my hands. My kid is playing on a chair and is about to fall onto the hard floor. I can catch her and save her, but only by dropping the heirloom so that it will shatter. Suppose the heirloom is particularly dear to me.

    It is not obvious to me that in such a case, upon dropping the heirloom to catch my kid, I actually desired to drop and shatter the heirloom in any way. I could have zero desires one way or the other about the heirloom, and the only desire I would have is to keep my child from being hurt, in which case I did not intentionally bring about the shattering of the heirloom, only my daughter's being saved from falling.

    There seems to be a distinction there; if you don't see it, I don't know how else I can argue except with more examples.

    ReplyDelete
  9. I suppose we will simply have to maintain the disagreement.

    There is a difference between desiring some states of affairs and being willing to allow or bring about some state of affairs' obtaining [for some subsequent state of affairs].

    I assume you would agree with the luck objection to libertarianism. If a person's choice cannot be explained in terms of their desires (or any other set of circumstances) then the person's choice appears to be a matter of chance. We cannot explain it(etc...).

    Now it seems to me that a rational creature will work backwards from goal to the first step in the process to achieving that goal (I think Reymond calls this the Teleological Principle in his discussion of supralapsarianism). So "when" God comes to the decree that men should fall into sin, we can ask "does God desire this state of affairs?" and say "Yes, he desires to bring it about, *in order that he might make atonement for men*." Without the latter clause the sentence might obviously be false. But taken together it seems obviously true. God's desire serves as an explanation for his action, not just of the act of atoning but for the entire plan of redemption.

    ReplyDelete
  10. I meant to add that I think that any example you can provide of doing some "undesirable" thing to achieve some ends could easily be explained in the same way: of course you did not desire to break the heirloom in itself (as an ends), but it still seems obvious to me that you did desire to break the heirloom in order to catch your daughter. The intention regarding the object serves as an explanation for your action.

    ReplyDelete