In this post I'm going to quote and comment on The Complete Street Epistemology Guide How to Talk About Beliefs (5/2016 ed.). Street Epistemology is a tactic used by atheists to undermine the faith of philosophically unsophisticated Christians.
I'll begin by responding to some stock questions. Then I'll comment on some other material in the guide.
Q. How can we figure out whether there is a reliable way to know that this is true?
A. That's not an easy question to answer. As Roderick Chisholm noted, some epistemologists begin with paradigm-examples of knowledge while other epistemologists begin with criteria or some methodology. There's a dialectical relationship between examples and criteria. They cross-pollinate.
I don't think either one can function an absolute starting-point. We can't begin from scratch. We have to have some knowledge to assess other knowledge-claims. We must begin in medias res. We must have instances of knowledge as well as intuitive criteria at the outset. On a Christian worldview, that's possible. God endows human minds with innate knowledge or instinctive criteria, such an a natural grasp of informal logic. In addition, he places us in a world governed in large part by ordinary providence, so that we can reliably generalize from representative samples of experience.
Q. Do you rely on faith to be confident about your religious beliefs?
A. Depends on what you mean by "faith". If you're using "faith" as a synonym for "belief", then I don't use faith to arrive at belief since that would be circular. Indeed, to pose the question with that definition in mind is prejudicial. You're defining faith in fideistic terms. I understand that atheists view Christian faith as fideistic, but that reflects the partisan perspective of the atheist rather than Christians, per se. So that's a loaded question by smuggling a pejorative atheist assumption into the terms of the question.
If, however, you're using "faith" as a synonym for the Christian worldview or belief-system, then we do, of course, we use our worldview or plausibility structure to assess particular claims.
Q. How confident are you that the belief is true?
A. If you're asking about Christianity, one way to answer is by process of elimination. I'm confident that the alternatives are false. Atheism is false. Buddhism is false. Hinduism is false. Islam is false. And so on and so forth.
Q. On a scale from zero to one hundred, how confident are you that your belief is true?
A. I don't think beliefs are strictly quantifiable.
Q. How did you (originally) conclude that this belief was true?
A. The formulation of the question is prejudicial. Why make the original process of belief-formation the frame of reference? Suppose I converted to Christianity as a teenager due to some pivotal experience or persuasive argument. However, 20, 30, 40 years later, I might well have additional reasons for my faith. Later and better arguments might replace earlier and inferior arguments.
Q. What are the top three things that make you confident that your belief is true?
A. That's simplistic. There are many lines of evidence feeding into my faith. And that can be difficult to untangle. Reasons blend with other reasons. Theistic proofs. Biblical archeology. Religious experience. The argument from prophecy. The argument from miracles. Answered prayer. And so on and so forth.
Q. What role does X have in your knowing that the belief is true?
A. The way the question is formulated slants the answer. But it isn't any one thing.
Q. How confident would you be in the belief without X?
A. That question artificially atomizes the belief-structure. But it doesn't rest or fall on one particular piece of evidence. It's not like pulling a strand on a knitted sweater, where it all unravels if you tug one strand.
In addition, apparent evidence to the contrary is not a good reason to instantly ditch your entire belief-system. Every philosophical position has difficulties. We try to work through difficulties. The question is whether there's a tipping point.
Q. What gives you the most confidence that your belief is true?
A. No one thing in particular. Take Newman's illative sense or Polanyi's tacit knowledge.
Q. When I asked whether you could be mistaken, I meant whether anyone—even the most intelligent and well-educated of people—could make an error in attributing the cause of an experience.
A. Of course, but the hypothetical possibility of error in general is not a rational basis for doubting any particular belief. That shouldn't be confused with evidence of error.
Q. What evidence would change your confidence in the belief?
A. If you're alluding to Christianity, there's a sense in which Christianity is hypothetically falsifiable. Christianity can't be true if one or more things contrary to Christianity are true. There is, however, no point in jumping down an endless array of imaginary rabbit holes to cultivate doubt for the sake of doubt. That's not a rational procedure, but an intellectual evasion.
Q. If evidence has no power to alter your confidence, are you really believing based on evidence in the first place?
A. "Evidence" is a value-laden category. We need to go back a step and ask ourselves what the world must be like for reason to be reliable, induction to be reliable, testimonial evidence to be reliable, sensory perception to be reliable, for logic to be necessary and universal. What kind of creatures must we be, what kind of world must we inhabit, for humans to have minds, for our minds to be in contact with reality?
There's a difference between the defeasibility of particular beliefs or truth-claims and a conceptual scheme on which the very concept of defeasibility depends. The principle of defeasibility has ontological commitments. Some things must be unquestionable to question other things. And reality must have a particular configuration for minds and extramental objects of knowledge to match up.
Q. How might we test the belief, in a way that would be difficult to pass if the belief were false?
A. That's a good question, but consider the underlying assumption. To test a belief presumes a standard of comparison. We can't start from nothing. We can't hold all our beliefs in suspense.
In that respect, empirical questions are secondary to metaphysical questions. Behind the empirical question is ontological question of what essential enabling conditions must be in place, and what metaphysical machinery must be in place to underwrite them, for us to have confidence about anything whatsoever.
Atheists act as if you can just bracket God and leave all the enabling conditions intact. But that treats the idea of God as if God is just one discrete truth-claim on which nothing of consequence depends, rather than a necessary truth-condition on which everything else depends. An atheist can still attempt to challenge that, but it's a much bigger challenge to a different kind of claim.
Q. How might we use faith to decide which claim is correct?
A. If by "faith" you mean the Christian worldview, then creation, revelation, and providence supply benchmarks for assessing individual truth-claims.
Q. Do humans ever misconstrue reality?
A. Obviously, yet recognition of error assumes that we're capable of accessing reality. But what must the real world be like for our cognitive equipment to be adequate?
Q. How does one being raised with this belief make it true?
A. It doesn't.
Q. Does the Hindu have faith that Vishnu is real?
A. A Hindu has a socially-conditioned, fideistic belief in Vishnu. However, the question is prejudicial because it treats Christian faith and Hindu faith as though those were analogous, which begs the question against Christianity.
The term "Street Epistemology" (SE) originates in Dr. Peter Boghossian's book, A Manual for Creating Atheists.
That exposes the ulterior agenda behind these faux innocuous questions.
Like everyone we make use of inductive reasoning and deductive reasoning, while being on guard for fallacies. Being human we too acquire many of our beliefs through testimony (while being aware of its problems), and cannot help but make intuitive coherentist evaluations of plausibility when encountering new claims. However, with Defeasibility Tests we emphasise falsifiability — the mode of justification that powers much of modern science. We also compare and evaluate the probabilities of competingexplanations using Bayesian inference, and turn to Occam's razor to favor the simplest process that would generate observed events. We'll even dig into the justification of extraordinary claims in a somewhat foundationalist manner, by following the chain of justification until it reaches ordinary claims, and seeing whether the inference holds up. One could also say Street Epistemologists are being pragmatic when we apply Outsider Tests, as we seek the practical consequences that enable us to adjudicate between competing claims.
i) Many philosophers would take issue with one or more of the assumptions driving Street Epistemology. So Street Epistemology has its own set of privileged assumptions. Criteria it takes for granted.
ii) Notice the appeal to Occam's razor against "extraordinary claims". One problem is that simplicity often involves a tradeoff between a simpler ontology and a simpler explanation. Eliminating entities may force a more convoluted explanation. For instance, what's simpler–a single Creator or a multiverse (not that those are mutually exclusive)?
Don't move on to examining the reliability of faith until you've agreed on what faith is. Most people concur with definitions that mean roughly "choosing to be more confident than you would be if you were relying solely on evidence." Anecdotally, we find most believers at least agree with the statement that "evidence brings you only so far, faith takes you the rest of the way (to knowing)." By agreeing to their positively-worded definition of faith as a way of knowing, they are less likely to then reject equivalent definitions that highlight its weakness.
Street epistemologists are bullies who attack soft targets.
The "faith as trust" definition makes sense if by "faith in God" one means "trusting God to fulfil certain promises", but it does not make sense if one means "trusting God to exist" - and yet often a believer will say "evidence alone is not enough to know God is real, you also need faith". they're talking about believing anyway, without the evidence.
There's a difference between having direct, independent evidence for particular claims and having indirect evidence that's dependent on direct evidence for the reliability of the source. Take a textbook on world geography. A student only has firsthand experience for a fraction of the claims in that book. But if the book is well-researched, then the book in itself is evidence for what it says about various localities.
You may meet sophisticated believers who use the word "faith" differently from popular usage. For example, they may use "faith" to mean the act of committing to a belief that one arrived at through evidence and reason — faith commitment as an act of doxastic closure. In this case, they aren’t claiming to use faith as a way of knowing their beliefs are true, but rather as an end state of some other way of knowing. They may also use "faith" to mean simply acting on what you consider likely to be true. You can work with them on their definition, recognizing at least in what ways it does not fit with common usage amongst believers.
That's a signal improvement.
The interlocutor may give a justification for their belief that relies on an equally extraordinary claim, such as a specific miracle. In this case think of yourself as a foundation inspector. Work with the interlocutor to determine whether their beliefs are built on solid ground or shifting sand. Dig deeper into the foundations of the interlocutor's belief system by asking, "What gives you confidence that X is true?" Keep digging until you reach a justification that is not based on something extraordinary.
Notice the biased classification of reported miracles and supernatural experience as "extraordinary claims". But what's the frame of reference? Is God extraordinary in a world where God exists? Are reported miracles extraordinary claims in a world where miracles actually occur? Unless a Street Epistemologist already knows what kind of world we inhabit, unless he knows that supernaturalism is false, his invidious comparison assumes the very issue in dispute.
By asking about how they originally formed the belief, they are less likely to fall back on answering "How do you make your belief sound reasonable to someone else?".
But it's often philosophically legitimate to distinguish between personal reasons for what I believe and reasons I might present to a second party. Some of my evidence might be based on firsthand experience, but a second party isn't privy to my firsthand experience. So I appeal public evidence if that's available.
Popularized by author John W. Loftus (a former Christian apologist turned atheist) in his book, "The Outsider Test for Faith: How to Know Which Religion Is True" , the Outsider Test for Faith helps interlocutors to see that their reasons for believing are no different from the reasons used by those from other religions, and thus not a good way to judge which religion is true.
Observe the built-in bias to "The Outsider Test for Faith"? Notice how it presumes all religious claimants are comparable, and the evidence or lack thereof is comparable. Far from being impartial, the "Outsider Test" is predicated on the falsehood of religion generally. That's not a neutral outsider test, but a partisan insider test, reflecting a secular viewpoint.
You can use an outsider test for any kind of evidence used to justify contradictory conclusions. For religions, this includes faith, numinous experiences, fulfilled prophecies, reported miracles, and answered prayers.
i) Which assumes that all religions have the same evidential appeals. This assumes that all religions have the same quality of evidence.
ii) Moreover, there can be kinds of evidence that eliminate naturalism without eliminating particular religious claimants. That's a separate issue. A different step in a cumulative case argument.
However it is most useful for extraordinary claims, such as miracles and supernatural phenomena, including:● Existence of one or more gods or immaterial persons (theism).● Phenomena that violate or suspend the operation of natural laws (supernaturalism, paranormal and psychic phenomena, miracles, karma).● Biological death does not end one's existence as a conscious being (afterlife, reincarnation, resurrection).● Numinous, revelatory, or mystical experiences [SEP: Religious Experience]● Personal experiences: answered prayers, "worked for me" therapies.● Testimony (e.g., anecdotes, tradition, authorities):
i) That's a blatantly sophistical ruse to preemptively discount any type of evidence that falsifies naturalism.
ii) And it does so by classifying certain phenomena as "extraordinary". By stipulative definition, those are relegated to the dubious status of "extraordinary claims". It creates a standing presumption against them.
iii) What's the justification for assessing answered prayer by first pigeon-holing answered prayer as an "extraordinary claim"? Why not just assess the evidence for answered prayer? Examine specific evidence for specific miracles.
For all their rationalistic rhetoric, Street Epistemologists don't actually follow the evidence. They have a priori filters to screen out evidence that runs counter to naturalism. The rationalistic posture is just for show. Defeasibility is a charade.
Testimony may be helpful in describing the evidence for a claim or how to obtain the evidence, but perceptions and memories are not generally reliable evidence on their own. Testimony is particularly vulnerable to errors and omissions by the reporter, intentional or not.
To say memory is generally unreliable is self-refuting. Atheists are dependent on their own memories, as well as collective memory.
Cameron Bertuzzi has written a series on Street Epistemology. Here's a link to PART ONE:
ReplyDeletehttp://capturingchristianity.com/street-epistemology-part-1/
Cameron has also has a written conversation with one here:
http://capturingchristianity.com/conversation-street-epistemologist/
Jonathan McLatchie was interviewed by a Street Epistemologist here:
https://youtu.be/LsLxlMv12XM (part 2 is linked in the description).
Speaking of atheists, an atheist Convention in Australia was cancelled because of lack of interest. The funny thing is that the convention was named "Reason to Hope".
Here's an article on its cancellation:
http://www.smh.com.au/comment/cancellation-of-atheist-shindig-is-a-disappointment-to-me--seriously-20171108-gzh3vh.html
Here's the website's cancellation and refund announcement [grin]:
http://atheistconvention.org.au/