Wednesday, September 16, 2009

Reppert Tries Good

In many recent blog exchanges, I've engaged Victor Reppert on the question of Calvinism and the problem of evil. During these exchanges, I have pointed out several times that Reppert never bothers to define what "good" or "evil" is, and I've also pointed out that there's really no purpose in discussing "the problem of evil" if one does not define "evil" in the first place.

I would have thought that this would be sort of obvious, especially for Reppert who is a professional philosopher. Apparently, however, Reppert feels no need to actually define his terms—making it very easy for him to engage in sloppy thinking without even realizing it. After all, part of the reason we define terms is so we can spot ambiguity. If you work with an undefined "evil" then it can morph depending on how you feel, such that an opening paragraph and a closing paragraph in a philosophical argument use completely different meanings of the term "evil" and yet seek to come to a logical conclusion. Not defining the terms is, obviously, poor argumentation.

Since Reppert posted another article about Calvinism and the problem of evil without defining his terms, I pointed out once again that he had not bothered to define his terms. In this case we might give him some leeway since he merely reposted an older blog post; however, given the fact that I have asked for his definition several times, I think such leeway is ultimately unjustified. Since his lack of defining terms has been shown many times, he ought to define his terms before posting another thing on the problem of evil from any perspective.

Reppert decided to respond to my request that he define his terms. He decided to first attack my definition of "good" before attempting what he claims is a definition. Unfortunately, rather than actually interact with my entire argument, presented for instance when I examined the Euthyphro Dilemma or my post on the definition of evil, Reppert decided to use quotes from one comment made on this post.

Sadly, Reppert didn't seem to read his own post, for his first question in response to what I had written was:
At the risk of becoming tiresome, I would have to ask what definition of God we are working with here?
The post I responded to was entitled: "Is there a moral obligation to worship a Calvinistic God? Or any other God for that matter?" Apparently, Reppert didn't think that maybe I was responding to his first question.

But it's actually even worse than that, for in that post in response to my previous comments Reppert had already said:
Of course the divine command theory has the problem of identifying God. The standard philosophical definition of God is a being who is worthy of worship in virtue of being omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good. But if "good" means "commanded by God" and "God" means a being who is, among other things, perfectly good, it looks like you've got vicious circularity here.
I note in passing that this paragraph is basically the entirety of Reppert's current response to me too.

If Reppert had bothered to actually read my arguments that I had linked in my comments before the one Reppert pulled out to respond to now, he would have seen that I already addressed the issue of identifying who God is. In my Euthyphro post, I said:
Now one could argue, as the Moral Philosophy site did, that that means that God could command slavery, genocide, holocausts or any number of such things. However, God could not have done so, for then God would have a different nature then the one He has. A different God could have commanded those things and been morally good in doing so; this God (Who happens to be the real God) cannot do so.
Apparently Reppert thinks that when Christians talk about God, they might mean Moloch or Vishnu.

In any case, the God of the Divine Command Theory is pretty obvious to spot. He's the God who gives the commands. I would have thought that to be self-evident.

Reppert then moves on to the only thing that resembles a definition (and sadly, he does think it is a definition). He writes:
In my view moral obligation is created by the fact that God creates us with an intended purpose which is identical to our good, in that we as humans flourish if we fulfill that purpose.
But this simply fails as a definition of good. This definition would not enable one to examine whether God Himself is good, for good apparently is fulfillment of the purpose for which God created us. Since God did not create Himself, nor did He have a creator, then under such a definition God cannot be good.

Secondly, such a definition of "good" is not equivalent to moral goodness. It is good of me to eat food when I am hungry, but it's hardly righteous of me to do so. If this is what Reppert implies by the moral obligation portion, then this definition remains unsatisfactory, for it is certain that God designed people needing food, yet who would consider eating breakfast to be morally good? If, on the other hand, Reppert only intends to define only what moral obligation is here, then he's got the cart before the horse for he is using the term "good" without defining it once again.

Thirdly, and quite damaging to Reppert, in order for us to use "good" in the above, we would have to know for what purpose God designed us. How would we know what that is…without God's commands? But wouldn't that make Reppert a closet Divine Command Theorist?

Fourth, and most damaging to Reppert, if God designed someone to be a vessel of wrath, then by the above definition Reppert has said such an intended purpose "is identical to our good," in which case there is absolutely no reason at all for Reppert to disagree with double-predestination on the grounds that it's evil. Even by his own (weak) definition above, fulfilling the purpose God intends for us is the definition of good. So when a reprobate fulfills his purpose and burns in hell, that's good by Reppert's above definition.

Note that at this point Reppert will be required to insert a qualifier. That qualifier will be: "No, it must be a good intention." At which point it will be demonstrated that the "fulfilling one's purpose" definition above does NOT define "good" at all because it already presupposes some other definition of good in "fulfilling one's good purpose."

Reppert continues:
Further, God acts in a way that is consistent with the pursuit of that good for all his creatures.
I shudder to think that Reppert seriously is asserting that if God does not act in a way that is beneficial toward man then God is committing evil (see next blockquote too). This is so obviously anti-Christian that I would think it absurd for a professing Christian like Reppert to think that God failing to live up to our goodness is what constitutes evil, rather than us failing to live up to His goodness. But sadly Reppert doesn't give me confidence that he sees this problem, so I mention it here.

Continuing:
Our good is to glorify God and enjoy him forever, evil is what gets in the way of that.
But again, under such a view, good or evil is meaningless of God. At best, Reppert can only use this to try to establish relative good and evil amongst mankind, but he can never examine the problem of evil for none of his "definitions" of good and evil extend to anything that God can do.

Reppert says:
On Calvinist theory there is a large gap between what makes God's character good, and what makes us good, a gap that cannot be explained in terms of a difference in God's wisdom or knowledge.
Well, yes there is a gap because men are sinners and God is not, and therefore what "makes us good" is Christ's righteousness imputed to us and our unrighteousness imputed to Him, which God does not need to be good.

But more specific to our current discussion, God is the standard of goodness; we are not. Yes, that makes a wide gap. But so what?

Reppert continues:
A native may believe that men in white coats bearing long needles are mean to little kids because he lacks knowledge that the men in the white coats possess, but the standard of goodness for natives and for missionary doctors is the same.
That is because both are human. Apparently, Reppert would put God under the Law, which was implemented as a tutor to bring us to Christ, as if God needed to be brought to Christ.

Reppert continues:
Piper seems concerned to respond to the charge that God's interest in his glory makes him selfish, since selfishness is a vice amongst humans.
There's a difference between the one who claims something as his own having not earned it and the one who claims something as his own after having earned it. As a liberal, Reppert will never grasp this. But to help others, the next time Reppert says, "I wrote C. S. Lewis's Dangerous Idea: In Defense of the Argument from Reason" I will point out that that's a pretty selfish thing to say. Who cares if Reppert deserves the title of "the author of the book C. S. Lewis's Dangerous Idea: In Defense of the Argument from Reason"? It would be selfish to attribute it to him and not also to me.

Reppert said:
If I were to read on someone's tombstone "He pursued his own glory single-mindedly throughout his life" I don't think I would think I was looking at the grave of someone I wish I had known. Glory hogs in basketball don't help the team win.
But once again Reppert reduces God to a mere man. He never considers that the reason God can be selfish for His glory is because God deserves glory for who He is, and because we are not God we do not have the same right to pursue our own glory.

But even worse, this trivializes what God does for us in the pursuit of His glory. He demonstrates greater love than we ever could by sending His Son to die for us while we are yet sinners; He shows mercy, justice, wrath, and love; He sends rain to the just and unjust alike. And Reppert is upset that God would do this for us with His own glorification—the very thing He most deserves—in mind?

Reppert says:
It seems to me that when you say God gives commands based on his nature, it is pretty clear that we don't have obligations to reflect all aspects of God's moral nature in our own conduct.
How could we? It's pretty clear that no matter how much you love someone, you will never die a substitutionary death for them, imputing their unrighteousness to yourself while imputing your righteousness to them, so that you take upon yourself the sins of another so that they might live. Maybe that's why God didn't command it of us, but He did ask it of His Son.

Reppert continued:
We might be rightly wrathful when someone we love is raped, but we aren't supposed to be looking for or artifically creating opportunities for us to exercise our attribute of being wrathful at evil…
Why look for artificial opportunities when natural occurrences abound? Secondly, so what? Again, we have already established that God's nature is not ours and that He can do things that we cannot. Why insist that God must be a man rather than God?

Reppert said:
So while divine commands are supposed to be based on the divine nature, the kind of people we are commanded to be fails to fully reflect the character of God, and there are actions on the part of God which are deemed right which, if parallel actions are performed by humans, they would contravene the commands of God.
But this last clause is true no matter what position you take. God does do things that He has commanded us not to do. And the first clause is only a problem if God has commanded us to fully reflect His character. He has not done so. He has given us the commands which we are to follow, and we do not have any right to add to them. For an easy example, God doesn't command us to take vengeance—He claims that as His own right. Engaging in vengeance surely is an aspect of character, isn't it?

6 comments:

  1. Is the Westminister Catechism wrong when it says the chief end of man is to glorify God and enjoy him forever? Because it doesn't look as if a Calvinist can unequivocably say that. That would mean that the persons in hell have not achieved their chief end, since they are not glorifying God and not enjoying him forever. It seems to me that a Calvinist has to say that the chief end of man depends upon whether or not you are elect.

    If a person goes to hell, you have to maintain that there is some fundamental, inherent purpose to their existence as a human being that they failed to achieve. But what sense does that make if God is in complete control of everything?

    ReplyDelete
  2. Well I suppose if you just want to completely change the subject we can discuss that. But it appears to me that Steve's already addressed that with you.

    I seem to remember him pointing out that

    A) sinners in hell do glorify God even if they do not "enjoy Him forever."

    B) The Confession says "man" as in "mankind" not "every single individual man." Illustrations abound. Consider football: if the chief end of the offense is to score, then according to you the center who has a 15-year career without ever once stepping into the end zone with the football must be a failure because he has never scored a single point, even if his team won 15 Superbowls during that time.

    Now you can continue to ask the same questions that have already been answered of you, and you can continue to not answer the questions that have been asked of you, and I won't mind at all. It shows everyone exactly how strong your argument really is.

    ReplyDelete
  3. "Apparently, however, Reppert feels no need to actually define his terms—making it very easy for him to engage in sloppy thinking without even realizing it."

    Shows the inseparable interconnectedness between semantics or linguistics and philosophy or logic. Or the importance of definitions to argument or rhetoric.

    But this is 101 stuff. And for Peter to remind Victor of that is not to Victor's credit.

    ReplyDelete
  4. B) The Confession says "man" as in "mankind" not "every single individual man."

    To use mankind collectively as opposed to divisively (on the whole vs. every single individual in the class), it must be the case that the majority of men in the class have the predicate "...enjoy Him forever".



    "Illustrations abound. Consider football: if the chief end of the offense is to score, then according to you the center who has a 15-year career without ever once stepping into the end zone with the football must be a failure because he has never scored a single point, even if his team won 15 Superbowls during that time."

    First of all, the chief end of the offense (and defense) is to win, and this predicate, as in any team sport, can only be applied to the whole and not each every member (players say "we won", not "I won!".

    And this points out how this example is disanalagous. "enjoyment" is something true of individual men, not men as a whole. If someone says "we enjoyed the football game", what someone says is false if anyone the term "we" quantifies over didn't, in fact, enjoy the foot ball game.

    That is, "enjoyment" can only be used divisively. Individual men enjoy God, not men "on the whole".

    ReplyDelete
  5. Derek said:
    ---
    To use mankind collectively as opposed to divisively (on the whole vs. every single individual in the class), it must be the case that the majority of men in the class have the predicate "...enjoy Him forever".
    ---

    What's your point?

    Derek said:
    ---
    First of all, the chief end of the offense (and defense) is to win,
    ---

    No, that's the chief end of the TEAM, which is why you had to add "and defense". The chief end of the offense is not to prevent the other team from scoring--it's to score.

    Derek said:
    ---
    ...and this predicate, as in any team sport, can only be applied to the whole and not each every member
    ---

    Which actually supports my argument. When a quarterback throws a touchdown pass, the lineman can say "We scored" just as much as the QB and the receiver, yet the lineman can go his entire career without ever once touching the football. He never once made it into the end zone. Yet it is still true that he achieved the purpose for which he was put on the field, for the offense scored points.

    And that's the whole point. Mankind as a whole can enjoy God forever--that is, it can be true in general of mankind--without every single man enjoying God, just as an offense can score points without every single member of the offense taking the football into the end zone.

    Derek said:
    ---
    If someone says "we enjoyed the football game", what someone says is false if anyone the term "we" quantifies over didn't, in fact, enjoy the foot ball game.
    ---

    Nonsense. We do, in fact, see this all the time. I live in Colorado, so when the Broncos won the Super Bowl it was no surprise to see "Denver celebrates" in headlines even though it is most certainly the case that not everyone in Denver cares about football. Indeed, it is quite likely that there are more people who don't care about football than do care about football in any given city, yet that doesn't alter the use of the collective "we." Nor does anyone other than the anal retentive find it problematic in the least.

    ReplyDelete
  6. "To use mankind collectively as opposed to divisively (on the whole vs. every single individual in the class), it must be the case that the majority of men in the class have the predicate "...enjoy Him forever".
    ---

    What's your point?"

    The point is: surely you don't think the vast majority of men will be "enjoying Him forever."

    So if "mankind" is meant in the collective sense, then then saying "...the chief end of man.. is to enjoy Him forever" is false.

    "No, that's the chief end of the TEAM, which is why you had to add "and defense". The chief end of the offense is not to prevent the other team from scoring--it's to score."

    Chief ends are always the SOLE purpose. Read some Aquinas. The chief end of everyone on a team, defense or offense, coach or player, is to win. All other ends are a means to this chief end. To say otherwise means that "winning" is not the chief end, which is false.

    "Mankind as a whole can enjoy God forever--that is, it can be true in general of mankind--without every single man enjoying God..."

    Agreed, so long as you admit that "general" supervenes on the "vast majority of men."

    "...Indeed, it is quite likely that there are more people who don't care about football than do care about football in any given city, yet that doesn't alter the use of the collective "we.""

    Are you really likening the WC to the loose and vague rhetoric of a newspaper?

    ReplyDelete