Tuesday, August 17, 2010

Final retribution

Here's a passage from a recent article by Oliver Crisp:

***************************************

[Quote] The Augustinian could adopt another approach, involving revision of one (or more) of these conditions. The obvious candidate is condition (c), which had to do with ‘The need for the display of both God’s grace and mercy and his wrath and justice in his created order’. But, the Augustinian might argue, it is important that the display of divine justice has some connection to desert. Were Christ to be the only human person upon whom divine justice was visited, as a vicarious substitute for sinners (as per Augustinian universalism), this would not have the right connection to desert because Christ does not deserve to be punished – he acts vicariously (and sinlessly) on behalf of sinful human beings deserving of punishment. There has to be some connection between the display of divine justice and the idea that (at least some of) those upon whom divine justice is visited are deserving of punishment. In order to reflect this, we could rephrase condition (c) as follows:

(c∗ ) The need for the display of both God’s grace and mercy and his wrath
and justice in his created order for some number of deserving humanity.

Let us call this the strict justice condition. There seems to be a good independent theological reason for thinking the strict justice condition is true. Unlike the Augustinian universalist argument outlined earlier, the strict justice condition requires that at least some of those upon whom divine justice is visited deserve to be recipients of that justice, which Christ is not. So the strict justice condition promises to deliver another reason for the Augustinian to resist universalism.

http://journals.cambridge.org/action/displayFulltext?type=1&fid=6906424&jid=SJT&volumeId=63&issueId=01&aid=6906416

HT: Paul Manata

34 comments:

  1. If Christ does not deserve to be punished and yet he is punished, that is itself an unjust act.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Ken,

    Only if you ignore voluntary sacrifice, at which point it is mercy.

    Suppose you owe me $1000 that you justly ought to pay. Suppose someone volunteers to pay that on your behalf. If I accept that, have I committed an injustice? Would you claim that I am unjust, or that the person who paid the debt was unjust? He didn't have to pay it, but did so willingly for his own reasons. As far as I'm concerned, I only need payment for the debt, and payment for the debt has been given.

    Where is this unjust?

    ReplyDelete
  3. Peter,

    Pecuniary debts can be transferred but not criminal debts. In the death of Christ we are not talking about the payment of a fine or a pecuniary debt, we are talking about execution. Is it just to execute an innocent person in place of the guilty? The issue is not whether the substitute volunteers; the issue is how can a just judge accept the substitution?

    ReplyDelete
  4. We're not talking about just an old "person," but the divine lawmaker who sentences himself to acquit others.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Steve,

    That still does not explain the justice of the act. If a judge decides to punish himself instead of the guilty, that may be his prerogative if he is sovereign over the law but it doesn't explain why the punishment is a) necessary or b) just. It would seem that the necessity of the punishment would have to be satisfy the demands of justice and yet it is itself an unjust act.

    ReplyDelete
  6. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    That still does not explain the justice of the act. If a judge decides to punish himself instead of the guilty, that may be his prerogative if he is sovereign over the law but it doesn't explain why the punishment is a) necessary..."

    It is necessary because:

    i) It is morally obligatory that injustices be rectified;

    ii) If the guilty are to be forgiven consistent with justice, then retribution must still be exacted (though not necessarily on the offender).

    "...or b) just. It would seem that the necessity of the punishment would have to be satisfy the demands of justice and yet it is itself an unjust act."

    i) To say vicarious punishment is itself an unjust act is arguing in a circular.

    ii) One of your problems is that you're appealing to moral intuition; however, many people find the idea of an innocent party volunteering to take the rap for a friend to be morally compelling.

    iii) Apropos (ii), this works in reverse. If Jim and John have a mutual friend in Justin, and Jim offends John, then Justin may be able to intercede on behalf of Jim, as favor between friends. Jim is the vicarious beneficiary of Justin's friendship with John. John wouldn't do it for Jim (with whom he's currently estranged), but he will do it for Justin. John is treating Jim as if Jim were Justin. As if he were entitled to the same treatment as Justin.

    ReplyDelete
  7. Steve,

    You say that the death of the innocent is necessary because:

    i) It is morally obligatory that injustices be rectified;

    How does punishing someone who is not guilty of the crime rectify justice? The act of punishing such a person is itself an injustice.

    ii) If the guilty are to be forgiven consistent with justice, then retribution must still be exacted (though not necessarily on the offender). ?

    The central element of retributive justice is that the person who commits deserves the punishment. C. S. Lewis said: the concept of Desert is the only connecting link between punishment and justice (God in the Dock, p. 288).

    You state:

    i) To say vicarious punishment is itself an unjust act is arguing in a circular. How so?

    ii) One of your problems is that you're appealing to moral intuition; however, many people find the idea of an innocent party volunteering to take the rap for a friend to be morally compelling. That is a red-herring. Yes it is noble for someone to volunteer to take the punishment in place of someone else but the issue is how does that constitute justice? If as Lewis says the concept of Desert is the only connecting link between punishment and justice, then to punish an innocent person is an injustice. If one does not deserve to be punished then to inflict punishment on the person is wrong because it is undeserved. All of your Reformed predecessors recognized this and attempted to justify the punishment of Jesus by means of imputation or mystical union (neither of which work by the way).

    As to your illustration: If Jim and John have a mutual friend in Justin, and Jim offends John, then Justin may be able to intercede on behalf of Jim, as favor between friends. Jim is the vicarious beneficiary of Justin's friendship with John. John wouldn't do it for Jim (with whom he's currently estranged), but he will do it for Justin. John is treating Jim as if Jim were Justin. As if he were entitled to the same treatment as Justin. That is all well and good but that is not the same as Justin suffering the penalty that Jim deserves. How would it satisfy John's sense of justice if he punished Justin in Jim's place?

    ReplyDelete
  8. Ken Pulliam said...

    "How does punishing someone who is not guilty of the crime rectify justice? The act of punishing such a person is itself an injustice."

    That doesn't advance the argument, Ken. You keep repeating the same claim. But that's the very contention in dispute.

    "The central element of retributive justice is that the person who commits deserves the punishment."

    That's a red herring. Whether the offender deserves to be punished is not the question at issue.

    "If as Lewis says..."

    That's not a reasoned argument. That's an appeal to authority. The opinion of C. S. Lewis doesn't settle anything. That, itself, is something to evaluate.

    Try that on Reppert, not me.

    "...then to punish an innocent person is an injustice."

    That's not unqualifiedly true.

    "That is all well and good but that is not the same as Justin suffering the penalty that Jim deserves. How would it satisfy John's sense of justice if he punished Justin in Jim's place?"

    Jim is getting better treatment than he deserves because John owes it to Justin. That illustrates the principle of transmissible merit.

    ReplyDelete
  9. Steve,

    You state that the contention that punishing an innocent person is itself an injustice is the very contention in dispute. Precisely and you have failed to show how it is not an injustice. If you read about retributive justice you will find that the key component is that the person who commits the crime deserves punishment. The evil act is deserving of punishment. To decouple punishment from guilt is contrary to retributive justice. It is blatantly unjust to put the punishment that someone deserves as a result of his evil act upon an innocent person. This is self-evident and is recognized by virtually all men. Again, go back and read your Reformed heroes, they all say that.

    As to your illustration it may illustrate "transferrable merit" but it doesn't illustrate "transferrable demerit." In order to show that penal substitution is legitimate, you need an illustration in which the demerit of one is transferred to another resulting in the just punishment of the innocent.

    ReplyDelete
  10. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    "You state that the contention that punishing an innocent person is itself an injustice is the very contention in dispute. Precisely and you have failed to show how it is not an injustice."

    i) And you have failed to show otherwise. Repetitiously asserting your claim doesn't make it so.

    ii) In addition, if all you're appealing to is moral intuition, then you can't prove your position. At best, you can cite illustrations which most readers find persuasive. But intuitive appeals lack the demonstrative value of, say, correspondence between belief that it's raining outside and rain outside.

    Hundreds of millions of people find penal substitution intuitively compelling, so you're intuition can pull rank on their intuition.

    The only thing that could pull rank is a divinely revealed norm.

    "If you read about retributive justice you will find that the key component is that the person who commits the crime deserves punishment."

    i) Once again, no one denies the fact that the offender deserves punishment. That's not the issue. The issue is whether a second party can punished in his stead. That's not the same issue.

    ii) And at the risk of stating the obvious, ethics is a value-laden discipline, so it's not as if everyone from Aquinas and Kant to James, Singer, and Ruse (among others) is going to agree on the key concepts.

    "The evil act is deserving of punishment."

    So you think the *act* is deserving of punishment rather than the *agent*.

    "To decouple punishment from guilt is contrary to retributive justice. It is blatantly unjust to put the punishment that someone deserves as a result of his evil act upon an innocent person. This is self-evident and is recognized by virtually all men."

    i) I didn't know that virtually all men excluded virtually all Christians. For historically, millions of Christians have found penal substitution morally satisfying. Same thing with OT Jews.

    And, of course, non-Christian sacrificial religion is also commonplace throughout history. The notion of vicarious atonement has been quite popular in time and place. That doesn't make it true, but it certainly falsifies your appeal to moral consensus.

    "Again, go back and read your Reformed heroes, they all say that."

    Imputation is a classic case of penal substitution.

    "As to your illustration it may illustrate 'transferrable merit' but it doesn't illustrate 'transferrable demerit.' In order to show that penal substitution is legitimate, you need an illustration in which the demerit of one is transferred to another resulting in the just punishment of the innocent."

    No, I don't. *You* have to show how the two are fundamentally asymmetrical.

    ReplyDelete
  11. Steve,

    Let me quote two "superstars" of Reformed Theology. I suppose that you respect John Owen and A. A. Hodge.

    Owen said:

    Sin hath other considerations,—namely, its formal nature, as it is a transgression of the law, and the stain of filth that it brings upon the soul; but the guilt of it is nothing but its respect unto punishment from the sanction of the law. And so, indeed, " reatus culpae" is " reatus poenae,"—the guilt of sin is its desert of punishment. And where there is not this " reatus culpae" there can be no " poena," no punishment properly so called; for " poena" is " vindicta noxae,"—the revenge due to sin. So, therefore, there can be no punishment, nor " reatus poenae," the guilt of it, but where there is " reatus culpae," or sin considered with its guilt; [emphasis mine] and the " reatus poenae " that may be supposed without the guilt of sin, is nothing but that obnoxiousness unto afflictive evil on the occasion of sin which the Socinians admit with respect unto the suffering of Christ, and yet execrate his satisfaction (The Works of John Owen, ed. William Goold, vol. V, 199).

    Hodge wrote:

    [W]e admit that, in the common judgment of all men, to regard and treat a man as responsible for a sin for which he is not truly responsible is beyond question unjust (The Atonement,p. 199).

    They at least recognized that there was a problem of injustice in punishing an innocent and sought a way around it.

    ReplyDelete
  12. Another thing Ken is forgetting is that God himself is an offended party in our sins.

    ReplyDelete
  13. Owen doesn't recognize any such problem. He begins by defining the "formal nature" of sin as a "as it is a transgression of the law."

    On that construction, what constitutes guilt, and liability to punishment, is a matter of what the law assigns.

    And he goes on to say, "There is, therefore, no imputation of sin where there is no imputation of its guilt...therefore, which we affirm herein is, that our sins were so transferred on Christ, as that thereby he became אָשֵׁם, ὑπόδικος τῷ Θεῷ, 'reus,' — responsible unto God."

    So, on his construction, it's possible for a second party to assume responsibility for the guilt of the first party.

    You may disagree, but that is hardly a concession on Owen's part.

    ReplyDelete
  14. Owen says that somehow the guilt or liability to punishment is to be separated from the actual sin itself. Only the guilt is transferred. This fails to recognize that there is no guilt without sin. IOW, guilt or liability to punishment is only present when the sin itself is present. That is why I say that doctrine of imputation is a legal fiction.

    ReplyDelete
  15. Also, Ken forgets the Bible teaches believers are united with Christ.

    ReplyDelete
  16. My point was that Owen, Hodge and virtually everybody recognizes that it is unjust to punish an innocent person. Thus, they come up with some scenario in which it would be just for Jesus to die (whether it is imputation or some other means). If Jesus died undeservedly as Crisp maintains in the article that you mention in the post, then that is an act of injustice. So Crisp's argument in his paper is flawed.

    ReplyDelete
  17. Of course only the guilt is transferrable. In the nature of the case, one party's *actions* (e.g. sin) aren't transferrable to a second party, for the second party didn't do what the first party did. He's not the same agent. So you can't say a second party did it. It's not attributable to him.

    But it doesn't follow from this argument that moral properties (merit/demerit) are intransmissible. For the same moral properties can be shared by more than one agent.

    No one denies that "there is no guilt without sin." That's not the question.

    The question is whether the effect of sin (guilt) is transmissible, and not what causes the effect. You keep confusing distinct issues.

    "My point was that Owen, Hodge and virtually everybody recognizes that it is unjust to punish an innocent person."

    You're confusing issues again. Owen, Hodge, et al. don't think it was unjust for God to punish Christ. That's a different issue from whether Christ suffered unjustly at the hands of Pilate or the Sanhedrin. It may be morally licit for a second party to permit another party to do something morally illicit.

    ReplyDelete
  18. Steve,

    How can guilt be transferred? Guilt is only caused by the demerit or evil action. If the acutal demerit is not transferred, then the guilt is not actual (it is a fiction).

    Crisp was talking about the justice of God and he argued that hell has to be real in order for God's justice to be demonstrated. He says it was not demonstrated in the death of Jesus because Jesus died "undeservedly." If Jesus died undeservedly, then his death was a miscarraige of justice.

    Owen and Hodge think that it would have been unjust to punish Jesus (an innocent person) unless somehow the guilt of sin was transferred to him. Once the guilt is transferred, then it becomes just. My point is that their position undermines the argument that Crisp is making in his paper.

    ReplyDelete
  19. Ken,

    Another thing that might help is for you to try to ground your concept of guilt in something. That is, you are asking moral questions about the transfer of guilt, but I do not know on what basis you can consider anyone to be guilty of anything in the first place. I mean, what is guilt in your view? What is morality? Are all moral conventions simply some version of a social contract? A personal feeling?

    Whatever it may be, is there any sense in which "guilt" is objective in your view? Does your morality have a transcendent nature such that it is not person or culture relative, but instead binding upon all people everywhere for all time? If not, then it seems whatever you define as "guilt" becomes irrelevant.

    On the other hand, if you hold to a relativistic framework of morality, then surely you can see that someone else's morality could disagree with yours with equal rights to claim to be moral; and that one such instance would be the person who claims that guilt can be transfered from a sinner to an innocent man for the purposes of justification. Even if that doesn't make sense to your morality, unless your morality is objective it doesn't matter.

    The point is, whatever your atheistic morality brings up will not be identical to what Christianity holds. But why should we Christians be concerned if our morality differs from atheistic morality? Indeed, Christians ought only be concerned if there is *NO* difference between the two!

    So if, in Christianity, we say that God has the right to accept the sacrifice of His Son as atonement for sinners, who are you to say that such a view is wrong?

    ReplyDelete
  20. Peter,

    I am assuming the Christian view of morality in my critique. The Bible says that God is upright and that all of his ways are just. (Deut. 32:4). The Bible also says that it is wrong to punish the righteous along with the sinner (Gen. 18:25; Eze. 18:20). So, in some way Jesus has to be considered guilty of sin in order to justly be punished. That is my point. Crisp says that the punishment of Jesus was undeserved. If that is true, then it was an unjust act. If it is false, then Crisp's argument about hell being necessary to demonstrate God's justice is false.

    I do not critique the Penal Sub. theory based on my own personal theory of ethics but on the moral values presented in the Bible, which according to the Bible is conveyed to all men through natural revelation (Rom. 2:14-15). I maintaind that the PST is inconsistent with the Biblical view of justice and ethics.

    ReplyDelete
  21. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    "How can guilt be transferred? Guilt is only caused by the demerit or evil action. If the acutal demerit is not transferred, then the guilt is not actual (it is a fiction)."

    i) You're confusing actual guilt with an actual guilty action, as if those are interchangeable. But deeds and moral properties of deeds are not conterminous, since more than one deed can exemplify the same moral properties. I already explained that to you. You're not advancing the argument.

    ii) How can Justin expect John to forgive Jim as a favor to Justin, when Jim did nothing to obligate John? How can John's obligations to Justin transfer to Jim? Yet, intuitively speaking, we regard that type of transaction as a defining feature of friendship. A will do a favor for C as a favor for B.

    "Crisp was talking about the justice of God and he argued that hell has to be real in order for God's justice to be demonstrated. He says it was not demonstrated in the death of Jesus because Jesus died 'undeservedly.' If Jesus died undeservedly, then his death was a miscarraige of justice."

    You oversimplify the issue. As I already explained to you, to say it was unjust for the Sanhedrin to convict Jesus doesn't mean it was unjust for God to allow (or decree) that event. You're not advancing the argument.

    "Owen and Hodge think that it would have been unjust to punish Jesus (an innocent person) unless somehow the guilt of sin was transferred to him. Once the guilt is transferred, then it becomes just."

    And transferring the guilt is, itself, just.

    "My point is that their position undermines the argument that Crisp is making in his paper."

    Crisp doesn't argue that it was wrong of God to punish Jesus. God is not the referent of the injustice.

    Try not to chronically oversimplify the issue.

    ReplyDelete
  22. Steve,

    You say that guilt without the demerit which causes the guilt can be transferred because: You're confusing actual guilt with an actual guilty action, as if those are interchangeable. But deeds and moral properties of deeds are not conterminous, since more than one deed can exemplify the same moral properties.

    What is the difference between "actual guilt" and "actual guilty action"?

    Since more than one deed can exemplify the same moral properties seems to be unrelated to the problem. Yes, there are many different deeds that could all share the same moral properties but how does that justify separating a specific moral property from a specific deed? It seems that what you need to be able to show is how the moral property of a deed can be disconnected from the deed itself. It is also not clear how even doing this helps you with the imputation of sins to Jesus. What precisely was imputed to him in your opinion? I take it not the deeds (sins) but the moral property (evil) that is attached to the deeds? If that is the case, how does Jesus escape the charge of possessing evil? What the Reformers typically say is that the liability to punishment (penal consequences of the deed) are transferred without the liability to fault (IOW, personal demerit connected with an evil deed). I maintain that is illogical and impossible.

    You say that Crisp when he speaks of Jesus dying "undeservedly" is talking about the Sanhedrin being unjust in convicting Jesus of blasphemy. Crisp nowhere mentions the Sanhedrin or any human actions for that matter in his paper. He is talking specifically about divine justice and how that needs to be demonstrated. He maintains that particularism is necessary because God needs to be able to demonstrate his justice and that justice was not demonstrated in the death of Jesus. Read his entire argument.

    You say: And transferring the guilt is, itself, just.

    How so? How would it ever be just to transfer the guilt of a crime committed by one person to another person? And how could one do so without transferring the actual demerit associated with the crime? Guilt only makes sense with there is something to be guilty of, otherwise its a "false guilt."

    ReplyDelete
  23. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    “What is the difference between ‘actual guilt’ and ‘actual guilty action’?”

    A moral property is not an action. Even if a moral property is the effect of an action, a moral property is not, itself, an action.

    “It seems that what you need to be able to show is how the moral property of a deed can be disconnected from the deed itself.”

    I already did that with my illustration of the three friends. Your only response was to postulate a possible asymmetry between transferable merit and transferable demerit. But you didn’t begin to demonstrate that postulate.

    “It is also not clear how even doing this helps you with the imputation of sins to Jesus. What precisely was imputed to him in your opinion?”

    The guilt of the elect.

    “I take it not the deeds (sins) but the moral property (evil) that is attached to the deeds? If that is the case, how does Jesus escape the charge of possessing evil?”

    Imputation doesn’t implicate his moral character, as if he’s personally evil.

    “Crisp nowhere mentions the Sanhedrin or any human actions for that matter in his paper. He is talking specifically about divine justice and how that needs to be demonstrated. He maintains that particularism is necessary because God needs to be able to demonstrate his justice and that justice was not demonstrated in the death of Jesus.”

    Crisp is a fairly orthodox Christian, so it’s not as if he’s impugning God’s character or rejecting penal substitution. He clearly doesn’t believe that God committed a grave injustice regarding the vicarious atonement of Christ. And in his article, he wasn’t attempting to justify penal substitution. That’s a presupposition of his article. Not something he tries to argue for in that particular article.

    “How so? How would it ever be just to transfer the guilt of a crime committed by one person to another person?”

    Take my analogy with the three friends.

    “And how could one do so without transferring the actual demerit associated with the crime?”

    There’s a difference between actual blame, and an actually blameworthy agent.

    ReplyDelete
  24. Steve,

    You say: A moral property is not an action. Even if a moral property is the effect of an action, a moral property is not, itself, an action.

    But it is descriptive of the qualitative nature of an action. There is still no way to separate the quality of an action from the action itself. If the action disappears or is not present, then the quality of the action also disappears.

    You say that The guilt of the elect was imputed to Christ and that Imputation doesn’t implicate his moral character, as if he’s personally evil.

    So its a legal fiction? He is treated as if he were guilty but in reality he is not? Again, since guilt has no meaning apart from the action that produced it, how can the two be separated. Simply saying as you have above that one is the act and the other is the moral value of the act does not help because as I stated, if there is no act, then there is no moral value. Moral value cannot be attributed to something that doesn't exist.

    I am very familiar with Crisp having read most of his articles and books. He is probably the most clever defender of the penal sub. theory today. While he doesn't say in his article that the punishment of Jesus was an injustice, he does say that it was not an act of justice and therefore for God's justice to be demonstrated, hell must exist. I think it is a blindspot on his part not to recognize that not only was the punishment of Jesus not an act of justice, it was in fact an act of injustice, if he suffered undeservedly as he claims.

    It seems you have the same problem because you want to say that Jesus was punished for the guilt of man's sin but not for the sin itself. Since guilt only has meaning when it is attached to a crime, it is impossible to separate the two.

    You say:

    There’s a difference between actual blame, and an actually blameworthy agent.

    Blame is an abstract idea and has no meaning unless attached to a person or thing. How do you transfer the blame for an action to one who did not do the action? You can only do so as an act of injustice.

    Your analogy of the three friends does not illustrate imputation or the penal sub. theory. You have an innocent person mediating for a guilty person and the offended person agreeing to forgive the guilty person and treat him as if nothing happened because of his admiration and respect for the innocent person. Yes, that can happen and it would be closer to Thomas Aquinas' view of the atonement than to the Penal Sub. theory. For in your analogy, the offended party is forgiving the guilty party on the basis of the superlative righteousness of the mediator not because the mediator is suffering the punishment that the guilty party deserves. In your analogy, the offended party is giving up his right to demand punishment.

    ReplyDelete
  25. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    “But it is descriptive of the qualitative nature of an action. There is still no way to separate the quality of an action from the action itself. If the action disappears or is not present, then the quality of the action also disappears.”

    Well, that’s a rather bizarre claim. Does the continuing existence of an effect depend on the continuing existence of a cause? Do we die the moment our parents die?

    “So its a legal fiction? He is treated as if he were guilty but in reality he is not?”

    i) You have an inability to grasp rudimentary distinctions. Guilt is hardly equivalent to an evil personal character. Guilt involves a violation of the law, or a violation of a duty to a superior.

    If a soldier defies a direct order from his commanding offer, and that’s a lawful order, then the solder is guilty of insubordination–yet the soldier may be morally justified in defying the order.

    ii) Also, the whole notion of a legal fiction is something of an oxymoron. The son of a king enjoys certain birthrights that a commoner does not, even though he’s no better than the commoner–and maybe worse. But he’s entitled certain prerogatives due to his ascribed social status. That’s not a legal fiction, for that’s social status defined by law in the first place. His relation to a second party (his royal father) automatically transfers the same regal standing to the son.

    “Again, since guilt has no meaning apart from the action that produced it, how can the two be separated.”

    Repeating the same tendentious denial doesn’t make it any truer on the tenth repetition. From the time you first commented on this post, all you’ve done is to paraphrase the same claim. That doesn’t rise to the level of a reasoned argument. You’re just moving in circles.

    “Simply saying as you have above that one is the act and the other is the moral value of the act does not help because as I stated, if there is no act, then there is no moral value.”

    There is an underlying act–Adam’s. The sins of the elect.

    “Moral value cannot be attributed to something that doesn't exist.”

    That’s absurd on the face of it. Are you claiming that we can’t make true, morally ascriptive present-tense statements about past events or individuals?

    “While he doesn't say in his article that the punishment of Jesus was an injustice, he does say that it was not an act of justice and therefore for God's justice to be demonstrated, hell must exist. I think it is a blindspot on his part not to recognize that not only was the punishment of Jesus not an act of justice, it was in fact an act of injustice, if he suffered undeservedly as he claims.”

    You continue to reiterate the same simplistic claim, contrary to my careful distinctions.

    ReplyDelete
  26. Cont. “It seems you have the same problem because you want to say that Jesus was punished for the guilt of man's sin but not for the sin itself.”

    That is not what I said. He is punished for the sin of a second party. He assumes the guilt of the sin.

    “Blame is an abstract idea…”

    No, it’s a moral property.

    “…and has no meaning unless attached to a person or thing.”

    Of course, “attached” is just a spatial metaphor.

    “How do you transfer the blame for an action to one who did not do the action?”

    I already told you.

    “You can only do so as an act of injustice. ”

    That’s not an argument. That’s a tape recorder on playback. Repeating yourself ad nauseum like a loop-tape does nothing to further the argument. You really shot your wad with the first comment. You have no fallback argument. Nothing in reserve.

    “Your analogy of the three friends does not illustrate imputation or the penal sub. theory. You have an innocent person mediating for a guilty person and the offended person agreeing to forgive the guilty person and treat him as if nothing happened because of his admiration and respect for the innocent person. Yes, that can happen and it would be closer to Thomas Aquinas' view of the atonement than to the Penal Sub. theory. For in your analogy, the offended party is forgiving the guilty party on the basis of the superlative righteousness of the mediator not because the mediator is suffering the punishment that the guilty party deserves. In your analogy, the offended party is giving up his right to demand punishment.”

    You’re missing the point. My analogy operates at a higher level of generality. I didn’t use that analogy as a specific model for penal substitution. Rather, I used that analogy to illustrate the broader principle of transmissible moral properties. The vicarious principle. In this case, a transmissible obligation. Penal substitution or vicarious atonement would be a special case of that broader principle. Try to follow the argument.

    ReplyDelete
  27. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    "I am assuming the Christian view of morality in my critique. The Bible says that God is upright and that all of his ways are just. (Deut. 32:4). The Bible also says that it is wrong to punish the righteous along with the sinner (Gen. 18:25; Eze. 18:20)."

    i) Your appeal to Gen 18:25 is equivocal. God is not the speaker. That's a quote from Abraham.

    ii) Your appeal to Ezk 18:20 is typical Arminian spooftexting. Have you bothered to read Daniel Block on that passage?

    ReplyDelete
  28. Steve,

    You say: Does the continuing existence of an effect depend on the continuing existence of a cause? Do we die the moment our parents die?
    Of course not but there has to be a cause before there can be an effect. Blame or guilt comes as an effect of a wrong act. It comes to the person who commits the act. If you try to separate the guilt from the act and apply the guilt to someone who did not commit the act, then you are guilty of a non-sequitur.

    You say: Guilt is hardly equivalent to an evil personal character. Guilt involves a violation of the law, or a violation of a duty to a superior.
    So if I violate the law, who is guilty? I am. Could you make someone else guilty of my violation? No, not unless they aided me in some way in violating it.

    You say that The sins of the elect is the underlying cause for which Christ is held guilty. You still have not explained how someone can be held guilty for the crime of another. You believe it because you think the Bible teaches it, not because it makes sense. It doesn't.

    You must not have read Crisp's article because his thesis is that unless there is a hell, then God's justice is never demonstrated. Thus, the death of Jesus is not a just act, that is why he calls it "undeserved." If someone receives punishment that they don't deserve, that is injustice.

    You say that Jesus was is punished for the sin of a second party. He assumes the guilt of the sin. But you have yet to explain how this is possible. You gave an analogy in which someone is treated as if they didn't sin because someone else mediated on their behalf but that in no way illustrates how someone can bear the guilt for something they did not do.

    You say that the analogy illustrates the broader principle of transmissible moral properties. but it doesn't. There is no transfer of moral properties in your illustration. The guilty person is released from punishment because of the intercessession of the innocent person. The guilt of the guilty person is not transferred to the innocent nor is the innocence of the innocent party transferred to the guilty. You need to come up with an analogy that actually illustrates what you are trying to prove.

    You object to my use of Gen. 18:25 because it comes from Abraham's mouth not God's. Are you saying that the truth expressed in Gen. 18:25 is not valid; it doesn't accurately reflect the nature of your God? You also apparently object to Eze. 18:20 as representing divine truth although you don't explain why. And you do not comment on Deut. 32:4 at all. Do you believe that your God is just and upright in all that he does? Do you believe that punishing a person for what he did not do is just?

    ReplyDelete
  29. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    “If you try to separate the guilt from the act and apply the guilt to someone who did not commit the act, then you are guilty of a non-sequitur.”

    That’s a category mistake. A non sequitur is a logical fallacy, involving an invalid inference.

    However, the relation between action and guilt isn’t like a logical syllogism. Rather, that’s a metaphysical relation of some sort. Likewise, cause-and-effect relations don’t occupy the same domain as premise/conclusion relations.

    “So if I violate the law, who is guilty? I am. Could you make someone else guilty of my violation?”

    That doesn’t follow. A superior officer can be held accountable for the actions of his subordinates–even if he was ignorant of their actions, much less an active participant.

    What makes a party legally culpable is simply a matter of how the law assigns guilt.

    “You still have not explained how someone can be held guilty for the crime of another.”

    Actually, I have–repeatedly. You simply lack the intellectual aptitude to grasp the explanation.

    “You must not have read Crisp's article because his thesis is that unless there is a hell, then God's justice is never demonstrated. Thus, the death of Jesus is not a just act, that is why he calls it "undeserved." If someone receives punishment that they don't deserve, that is injustice.”

    Are you just too dense to register an explanation, even after it’s been repeatedly explained to you?

    There are situations in which it is morally licit for one party to permit another party to do something morally illicit. Do you need some concrete illustrations? Is that your problem? I can try to help you out if you need me to walk you through the process.

    ReplyDelete
  30. Cont. “You gave an analogy in which someone is treated as if they didn't sin because someone else mediated on their behalf but that in no way illustrates how someone can bear the guilt for something they did not do. You say that the analogy illustrates “the broader principle of transmissible moral properties.” but it doesn't. There is no transfer of moral properties in your illustration. The guilty person is released from punishment because of the intercessession of the innocent person. The guilt of the guilty person is not transferred to the innocent nor is the innocence of the innocent party transferred to the guilty. You need to come up with an analogy that actually illustrates what you are trying to prove.”

    You evince a completely superficial grasp of the issues. It is not simply a question of Justin interceding on behalf of Jim. Rather, it’s also a question of what qualifies him to play the role of intercessor. Because Justin is John’s friend, John has certain obligations to Justin.

    And on that basis, John will do something for the undeserving Jim for the sake of the deserving Justin. John doesn’t owe it to Jim, but because he owes it to Justin, John is obliged to treat Jim, the guilty party, as if Jim were Justin, the innocent party. So, yes, that illustrates the transitivity of moral properties.

    “You object to my use of Gen. 18:25 because it comes from Abraham's mouth not God's. Are you saying that the truth expressed in Gen. 18:25 is not valid; it doesn't accurately reflect the nature of your God?”

    i) You used that as leverage with Christians, as if anything the Bible says is true merely because you can find it said in Scripture. But while Scripture is a true record of what people say, not everything people are recorded to have said is true.

    Therefore, the truth of Abraham’s statement wouldn’t follow from the bare fact that the narrator of Genesis recorded that statement. For that you need an independent argument.

    ii) For that matter, Abraham’s experience illustrates the vicarious principle in the sacrificial animal that takes the place of Isaac.

    “You also apparently object to Eze. 18:20 as representing divine truth although you don't explain why.”

    Try not to be quite so dim. Did I say Ezk 18:20 was false? No. I said your interpretation of Ezk 18:20 was false.

    “And you do not comment on Deut. 32:4 at all. Do you believe that your God is just and upright in all that he does? Do you believe that punishing a person for what he did not do is just?”

    I don’t comment on Deut 32:4 because that was hardly meant to contravene the vicarious principle. After all, much of the Mosaic cultus is based on the vicarious principle. Your isolated prooftexting is acontextual.

    ReplyDelete
  31. According to Ken, "The notion that it is wrong to punish an innocent person is a basic intuition that all men possess and it seems to be present in man from infancy. I believe the notion is present in man due to the way our brains have evolved..."

    http://formerfundy.blogspot.com/search/label/A.%20A.%20Hodge

    But, of course, that's entirely inadequate to validate the intuition. At best, that would only account for the origin of the intuition. But that doesn't begin to show how the intuition is true.

    Indeed, if this moral intuition is simply the byproduct of naturalistic evolution, then it's an illusion. Natural selection has tricked us into believing that, but it doesn't correspond to any objective moral facts.

    ReplyDelete
  32. Ken has also said, "I believe that the idea of Jesus Christ dying for man’s sin has its origin in the ancient concept of offering human sacrifices to a deity. We know human sacrifice was common in ancient times."

    http://formerfundy.blogspot.com/2009/10/human-sacrifices-and-death-of-jesus.html

    But if so, then this directly contradicts his appeal to a universal moral intuition against the vicarious principle.

    ReplyDelete
  33. Steve,

    I think we have reached the end of the road here. You think that guilt can be transferred without the demerit which caused the guilt and I don't.

    As far as the intitution that it is wrong to punish an innocent person being invalidated by the practice of human sacrifice, here is the answer. Many people will violate their moral intuitions if they are told by a superior, especially what they believe to be a deity, to do so.

    ReplyDelete
  34. KEN PULLIAM SAID:

    “You think that guilt can be transferred without the demerit which caused the guilt and I don't.”

    Demerit doesn’t cause guilt. Sin cases guilt. Or law-breaking. Guilt and demerit are synonymous.

    “As far as the intitution that it is wrong to punish an innocent person being invalidated by the practice of human sacrifice, here is the answer. Many people will violate their moral intuitions if they are told by a superior, especially what they believe to be a deity, to do so.”

    i) That’s a classic example of someone who adjusts the evidence to accommodate his theory, rather than adjusting his theory to accommodate the evidence.

    You postulate a universal moral intuition. Then, in the face of counterevidence, you postulate a motive to make the counterevidence fit your original postulate.

    But unless you held a séance to interview the individuals in question, you’re in no position to say they were only acting under orders, in violation of their conscience.

    Where’s your evidence that all of them were both acting under orders and violating their conscience? Do you have cuneiform polling data from the ANE?

    ii) Moreover, your ad hoc explanation only pushes the question back a step: if subordinates only did it because their superiors made them, then why did their superiors issue the orders in the first place? Were their superiors violating their own conscience? Since you don’t believe a real deity told them to do it, what’s your explanation? Why did they believe that was a divine injunction?

    iv) Finally, your entire objection is gutted by your evolutionary ethics. Even if natural selection conditioned us to entertain these moral intuitions, natural selection is amoral. Therefore, natural selection can’t provide the moral warrant for these moral intuitions. The product of an amoral process is an amoral product. So you utterly failed to ground the moral intuition which you rely on to attack penal substitution.

    ReplyDelete